Skip to content

Is There Patient Autonomy In Jewish Law?

Patient autonomy, the right of a patient to determine his or her mode of medical treatment or to reject it, is a sine qua non of modern medical ethics.  Indeed, many of our most fundamental and universally-accepted medical practices are rooted in patient autonomy: informed consent, truth telling, risking or rejecting hazardous (and even some basic) procedures or surgery, and advance directives, such as living wills or health care proxies.  Patient autonomy is actually another aspect of individual autonomy, a doctrine central to our constitutional tradition.  In 1914, Judge Cardozo articulated this concept:

“Every human being of adult years and sound mind has a right to determine what shall be done with his body and a surgeon who performs an operation without his patient’s consent commits an assault for which he is liable in damage.”1

Since a patient must be able to determine what medical procedure may (or may not) be performed on his body, he must be fully informed in advance of the available treatment options and he must consent to any procedure.  In fact, “unless a physician discloses certain information to a patient before performing a procedure, the patient is entitled to damages even if the procedure was performed correctly.  The exact scope of disclosure demanded of the doctor is not clear, but most courts require that the patient be told the diagnosis, the nature of the proposed procedure, the risks and benefits of the procedure, the available alternative procedures and their risks and benefits, and the consequences of not having the procedure.”2

Disclosure to the patient and his subsequent consent forms the basis of what is commonly referred to as “informed consent,” a term first used in 1957.3  It is, of course, axiomatic, that when the patient is informed of his diagnosis, he be told his “true” condition–clearly and candidly; otherwise, he could not possibly make a proper determination regarding the future course of his treatment.  But his disclosure also raises some ethical concerns of truth telling, such as when the patient’s diagnosis is terminal and his mental/emotional state is so fragile that this bad news might overwhelm him, seriously affecting his physical or psychological well-being.  Finally, patient autonomy recognizes the right of an individual to request certain medical treatments or withhold them should he become incapacitated if he expresses them in an advance directive.  For example, an individual may direct, in a living will, that he refuses cardiac resuscitation and mechanical respiration should he become incapacitated (i.e., incapable of making is own decisions) and is suffering from an “incurable or irreversible mental or physical condition with no reasonable expectation of recovery.”4  Clearly, then, the concept of patient autonomy is pivotal to contemporary medical ethics and practice.

A Jewish Legal Perspective

At first glance, one might conclude that there is no patient autonomy in Jewish law.  Since this doctrine is predicated on the “right to determine what shall be done with (one’s) body,” it is understood that one has some sort of proprietary interest in his body: it belongs to him to do as he pleases.  Yet, no less an authority then Maimonides declares, “the soul of this murder victim is not the property of the avenging relative but rather that of the Holy One, blessed be He…”5  Man does not “own” his body; it belongs to G-d.  Indeed, while our society recognizes personal autonomy as a cardinal principle, it is not absolute.  As Rabbi J. David Bleich so eloquently observes:

“Despite our society’s commitment to individual liberty as an ideal, it recognizes that this liberty is not entirely sacrosanct.  Although there are those who wish it to be so, self-determination is not universally recognized as the paramount human value.  There is a long judicial history of recognition of the State’s compelling interest in the preservation of life of each and every one of its citizens, an interest which carries with it the right to curb personal freedom.  What the jurist calls a ‘compelling state interest’ the theologian terms ‘sanctity of life’.  It is precisely this concept of the sanctity of life which, as a transcendental value, supersedes considerations of personal freedom…..Were autonomy recognized as the paramount value, society would not shrink from sanctioning suicide, mercy killing, or indeed consensual homicide under any or all conditions.”6

Other Jewish authorities, however, maintain that man has some autonomy to make personal medical decisions.  One of their most compelling sources is found in the Talmud (Sanhedrin 73a) concerning the obligation to restore a lost article to its rightful owner.  The Talmud reasons that if one is obliged to return lost property to its owner, then he must certainly restore that “owner’s” life and health,7 wherever possible.  Based on this passage, these authorities conclude that if the rightful owner chooses to abandon his property and not seek its return, the seriously ill patient, too, may forego the restoration of his health, under certain circumstances.8

While the sources for patient autonomy may be a subject of debate, the rights of Jewish patients to determine the course of their medical treatment are well-documented in the Talmud, Codes, and Responsa.  Rabbinic sages recognized long ago that one has an obligation to protect his health, based on the Biblical imperative–“Only watch yourself, surely watch your soul…(Deut. 4:9) which Maimonides9 and others say refers to safeguarding one’s health.  Indeed, it has been suggested that one who “watches” his health is treated in Jewish law as a bailee10(shomer), who must make every effort to protect the article he is given from loss or damage.  Since the Bible enjoins one to safeguard his body and physicians have been granted the authority to heal,11 it follows that one may seek medical treatment from a recognized physician and, of course, pray for his health.  Carrying the analogy further, when the obligation of watching the article becomes onerous, in cases where the burden far exceeds the benefit, one need not continue his role of bailee.  Similarly, in the case of a terminally ill patient, where the costs of sophisticated life support systems or experimental treatments are almost prohibitive, the patient may not be required to avail himself of these measures.12

Patient autonomy in Jewish law goes beyond the right to seek standard medical care when necessary; it allows a seriously ill patient to request a high-risk procedure (i.e., where he may die immediately as a result of that procedure) when there is a possibility of long-term survival.  Recent  rabbinic responsa find Talmudic precedent to this notion of one’s risking his immediate life (lit, “hourly life”) when there is a possibility of long-term (lit, “enduring indefinitely” or “perpetual”) survival.13  The Talmud (Avodah Zarah 27b) raises the issue of whether an individual may risk his life by receiving potentially life-saving treatment from a heathen physician who may kill him.  May he risk his certain short-term life of a day or two14 against the possibility of a long-term cure?  The Talmud rules that he may risk his short-term survival because “we are not concerned about hourly life” when there is a possibility of long-term survival.  The remarkable degree of patient autonomy in this case is underscored in Tosafot.  While the general Talmudic principle is that one may not risk a “certainty” in favor of a “doubtful” possibility (ayn safek motzi midei vaday), “in this case, we disregard the certainty (of the patient’s short-term life) in favor of the doubtful (long-term survival)”15

The right to refuse medical treatment clearly demonstrates patient autonomy; it, too, is recognized in Jewish law.  The source of this concept is also found in the Talmud, (Ketubot 104a) which describes the fatal illness of the great Rabbi Judah the Prince, known simply as “Rebbe”.  Rebbe’s pious maidservant, upon seeing her master’s suffering, prayed for his demise, and even interrupted his students from praying for his life.  Since the Talmud does not criticize her conduct, or in any way reject it, Rabbenu Nissim, a major Talmudic commentator, concludes, “There are times when one should pray for the sick to die, such as when the sick one is suffering greatly from his malady and his condition is terminal…”16  Contemporary authorities have applied this passage to the treatment of the critically ill in extreme pain, by allowing them to refuse “extraordinary” life-saving measures, and to receive intensive doses of pain-killers.17  Indeed, the great Rabbi Chaim Ozer Grodzinski, the leading rabbinic authority of pre-war Europe, determined that a patient who is critically ill may refuse surgery.  R’Chaim Ozer reckoned with the patient’s wishes.18

The ability of a live donor to donate non-vital organs or parts of his body, such as bone marrow or kidneys, clearly demonstrates that he has a proprietary interest in his body since one may not donate what does not belong to him.  Of course, organ transplants are a relatively recent development, and one would think it virtually impossible to find a precedent or sources in Jewish codes.  Yet, contemporary authorities have found a source in a Responsum of the Radbaz.19  The Radbaz was posed this most poignant question: a gentile authority requests that a Jew allow him to amputate one of his non-vital limbs or he will execute one of his friends.  May he permit this amputation in order to save his friend’s life?  The Radbaz ruled that he is not required to allow the amputation, unless he is motivated out of piety; however, if any way he may be risking his life by allowing the amputation, he is regarded as a “pious fool” if he permits it.  The Radbaz summarizes his position most succintly: “his doubtful (risking of his life) supersedes the certain (saving) of his friend’s life.”20 Contemporary authorities derive from this ruling that bone marrow transplants and, according to most opinions, kidney transplants are permissible in instances where there are no substantial risks to the donor.21

The advance directive is the document of patient autonomy.  In situations where the patient has become incapacitated and is no longer competent to make medical decisions, two types of advance directives were developed to enable the patient to direct his medical treatment in advance:  living wills and health care proxies. 

A living will is essentially a document prepared by a competent adult which instructs medical personnel regarding utilization of various procedures in the event that the adult becomes incapacitated.  Generally, the “will” is utilized as a directive to withhold or withdraw treatment in advance of an “incurable or irreversible mental or physical condition with no reasonable expectation of recovery”.22  In this document, individuals may specify forms of treatment that they would refuse such as cardiac resuscitation, mechanical respiration, tube feeding, antibiotics, and maximum pain relief.  While the “living will” could be used to request that these and other treatments be utilized, in practice, this is rarely the case.  By contrast, the health care proxy does not necessarily relate to various types of anticipated medical treatments.  It is simply a legal form to appoint a trusted individual to serve as a proxy or health care agent to make medical treatment decisions on behalf of the principal who signs the form.  The proxy operates with a power of attorney to make these decisions in the event that the principal becomes incapacitated.  It is best that the principal discuss his feelings with his proxy about which treatments should be taken or withheld, so that the latter will decide in accordance with the wishes of the former.

Upon careful analysis, neither of these advance directives is ideal.  The living will, precisely because it is so specific, tends to be somewhat rigid.  No one can possibly anticipate with certainty every medical contingency; in fact, one’s specific directives may later prove to be inapplicable or inappropriate.  As a result, the principal is “locked in” to an irrevocable treatment mode which may be medically contraindicated once he has become incapacitated; indeed, if he could talk, he might well reconsider his decision.  Another consideration:  in the fast-paced world of medical technology, new drugs and treatments might appear that would have impacted on his original directives.  The inflexibility of his living will might not allow for these developments.

By contrast, the great advantage of the health care proxy is its flexibility, which better allows for changing diagnoses and medical breakthroughs.  This flexibility is created by giving great latitude to the proxy — and this broad power (of attorney) also poses its greatest danger.  To wit:  Agudath Israel, a major advocacy of her I was a huge I do anything I can you are a living Wednesday and is in so you money in a him it was to go through Wednesday as a moment that I was no him in a him in a diamond with a while he was a little Wednesday and a matter of his eye and is a nice and is in a what my house in a live in a so I think in the materials and his live with some pain and is in the him in a him not uncommon to him was to him in the money in a him in if him a yet in the him in a him in okay I’m definitely inhim a group for Orthodox Jewry, objects to the N.Y. health care proxy bill primarily because it accords too much authority to agents to decide the fate of the patient. 

   Jewish law has been accused by some ethicists and reform-minded secularists of being paternalistic. In their opinion, patient autonomy in Jewish law is non-existent.  As a result, “patients are treated as if they are not capable of making decisions about medical problems: they are too ignorant medically speaking, and such knowledge as they have, is too partial in both senses of the word.  Thus, they are unlikely to understand the situation even if it is explained to them and so are likely to make worse decisions then the doctor would.”23  These critics claim that Jewish law substitutes the judgement of the rabbi and/or the doctor for that of the patient, thus violating his right of self-determination.

As we have seen, Jewish law generally recognizes and supports the concept of patient autonomy.  A patient may seek certain hazardous medical treatments, even where he may be risking his life in the hope of achieving a long-term cure.  In some cases, he may even reject life-support systems, surgery, and radiation or chemotherapy.  He may execute an advance directive.  Finally, according to many authorities, he may donate a non-vital organ or body part when he does not jeopardize his own health in the process.

In conclusion, we must remember that the Jewish patient is to be treated no differently than any other Jew: he, too, is governed by Jewish codes.  To the extent that the observant Jew submits to Jewish law as an expression of G-d’s will, he relinquishes a degree of autonomy.  However, within the parameters of Jewish law, his feelings and wishes must be honored.  Rabbis and doctors should not dictate to him.  Rather, the patient is duty-bound to first consult expert medical opinion regarding his diagnosis and treatment alternatives and then seek authoritative rabbinic guidance, as he would in any other critical matter.  Then, and only then, will he be able to exercise his free will to choose or refuse medical treatments and to provide truly informed consent in full accordance with his religious commitments.

FOOTNOTES

  1. Scholendorf v. Society of New York Hospital, 211 N.Y. 125, 129-30, 105 N.E. 2nd 92, 93 (1914)
  2. Sprung CL, Winick, BJ: Informed consent in theory and practice: legal and medical perspectives on the informed consent doctrine and a proposed reconceptulization. Critical Care Medicine 1989; 17(12)1347
  3. Salgo v. Leland Stanford Jr. University Board of Trustees, 154 Cap. App. 2d 560, 317 P.2d 170 (1957)
  4. From the generic text of the living will, prepared by the Society for the Right to Die, New York, 1990
  5. Mishnah Torah, Rotzeach 1:4. See also Radbaz on Mishnah Torah, Sanhedrin, 18:6, Sefer Chasidim 723; Shulchan Aruch Harav, Nizkei Haguf V’Nefesh 4; Responsa of Rivash 484; Chazon Ish, Nizikin, 19:5; and Igrot Moshe, Yoreh Deah, Volume 2, 174:3
  6. Bleich, J.D. The moral obligations of the physician in rabbinic tradition.  Doctor’s decisions: ethical conflicts in medical practice, Oxford University Press, 1989:219
  7. Maimonide’s Commentary to the Mishnah, Nedarim 6:8.  Also, Teshuvot Atzei Ha-Levanon, 61, who extends this passage to include restoring health in non-life-threatening situations.  See also Halacha Urefuah, Volume 2, pp. 133-134.
  8. HaKometz Mincha on Minchat Chinuch, Mitzvah 237 and Hochmat Shlomo to Choshen Mishpat, 426.  See also article by Rabbi Hershel Schachter, appearing in the Beit-Yitzchak Journal, 5746 issue.
  9. Mishnah Torah, Rotzeach, 11:4.
  10. As heard from Rabbi Dr. J. D. Bleich, interpreting the Ran to Nedarim 40a, at a lecture on 4/19/90.
  11. Yoreh Deah 336:1, based on Baba Metziah 31a
  12. Rabbi Shlomo Zalman Auerbach rules that a terminal cancer patient whose disease has metastasized may refuse extraordinary treatment, such as radiation or chemotherapy.  Similarly, a diabetic whose leg was amputated as a result of his illness may refuse the amputation of his other leg, even though gangrene has set in and he will die imminently without the operation.  In both these instances, the medical procedure will not reverse the underlying condition, and the patient may, therefore, refuse it.  (Cited by Dr. A.S. Abraham in Halachah Urefuah, 2:189.) See also Igrot Moshe, Chosen Mishpat, 2:74.

The Shvut Yaakov (Orach Chayim 1:13) declares that when a physician is unable to reverse a patient’s terminal condition and cure him, he no longer has the Torah’s sanction to practice medicine on that patient (reshut l’rapot, Baba Kama 85a), and his treatment does not fulfill the mitzvah of saving lives.  Since the mitzvah of expending money to save another’s life is derived from the verse, “do not stand idly by the blood of your neighbor” (Leviticus 19:16, as interpreted in Sanhedrin 73a), and this verse applies only where one is saved from certain death or, as a minimum, has his health restored (i.e., curative, not merely palliative), then we suggest that a terminal patient need not impoverish himself, or spend excessive monies to avail himself of experimental drugs, high-tech treatments and the like.  However, if there  is a reasonable possibility that this treatment will save his life, he may borrow money and pay interest (Yoreh Deah 160:22); indeed, according to the Rivash (387), he must expend his entire wealth since he wishes to avoid transgressing a negative commandment thereby.  The (Chavot Yair (139), however, opines that in the case of a negative commandment of a passive nature (lav sheayn bo maaseh, i.e., where no overt act is required to transgress), one need not expend more than he normally would to avoid violating a positive commandment (Cited in the Novellae of R’Akiva Eiger to Yoreh Deah, 157:1).

  1. Ahiezer, 2:16; Binyan Tzion 1:111; Beit Meir (Yoreh Deah) 339:1; Tzitz Eliezer, 4:13 and 10:25 and Igrot Moshe, Choshen Mishpat Volume 7, 74:5.  However, note the Shvut Yaakov, 3:75, who qualifies the decision by requiring a majority of expert medical opinion with the approbation of the leading rabbinic authority in the city.
  2. Rashi, ad loc.
  3. Tosafot, ad loc. See also Ritva on this passage who notes “that we are not concerned about this (short-term life), since there is a possibility of a complete cure we must do what is best for him.”  This case, according to the Vilna Gaon, is accepted as the source for the legal norm (Biur Hagrah to Yoreh Deah, 155:1, note 5.)  For a comprehensive review of hazardous medical procedures in Jewish law, see Rabbi Bleich’s Contemporary Halachic Problems, Volume 2, pp. 80-84.
  4. Nedarim 40a.
  5. Halachah Urefuah, Volume 2, p.189, in an article entitled, “Treatment of a Moribund Patient and Establishing the Time of Death” by Dr. A. S. Abraham.  Also, Igrot Moshe, Choshen Mishpat, Volume 7, 73:2.
  6. From a communicaton by the late Rabbi Yisroel Gustman, a member of Vilna’s Rabbinical Court, to Rabbi Dovid Cohen.
  7. Responsa 3:625 cited in Pitchei Teshuva to Yoreh Deah 157:15.
  8. See the S’ma on Choshen Mishpat 426:1 who cites a Yerashalmi which requires one to place himself in doubtful danger to save his friend who is in certain danger.  The Beit Yosef also quotes this source and explains it in accordance with the general principle–his friend who is in “certain” danger takes precedence over his own “doubtful” risk–ayn safek motzi midei vaday.  Yet, surprisingly, in normative Jewish law, this source is rejected:R’Yosef Caro does not refer to it in the Shulchan Aruch, and it is not mentioned in any of the major, primary sources (i.e., Rif, Rambam, Rash or Tur).  The Pitchei Teshuva (ad loc, note 2), citing the Agudat Ezov, echoes the Radbaz: “his doubtful risking of his life supersedes the certain (saving) of his friend’s life.”  In other words, one should not risk his own life (safek pikuach nefesh) to save his friend’s life because to do so would be tantamount to declaring that his “friend’s blood is redder than his”; thus one’s own life takes precedence. (chayecha kodmin, Baba Metziah 62a)
  9. Both the lgrot Moshe Yoreh Deah, Volume 2, 174:4 and Tzitz Eliezer, 10:25 permit kidney transplants to save a Jewish life, providing that there is no substantial risk to the life of the donor.  According to the latter in another opinion (9:45), a team of expert physicians must carefully determine that there is no life-threatening risk to the donor.  The Yechaveh Daat 3:84, of Rabbi Ovadiah Yosef, concurs.  (See also his article in Halacha Urefuah, Volume 3, pp. 61-63).  However, the Minchat Yitzchak, 6:103, prohibits kidney donations because of the immediate danger to the donor (transplant surgery) and possible long-term risks (failure of the donor’s remaining kidney).

In the case of a bone marrow transplant, where there is almost no risk to the donor, all authorities agree that such surgery is permissible.  Indeed, according to Rabbi Shlomo Zalman Auerbach, “it is a mitzvah for a relative to donate in this situation to save the life of a fellow Jew.”  (Nishmat Avraham, Yoreh Deah, pg. 264.)

  1. From the generic text of the living will, prepared by the “Society for the Right to Die,”  New York, 1990.
  2. R. Gillon, Philosophical Medical Ethics, 69, (1986).  While this citation does not refer to paternalism in Judaism per se, it provides a philosophical justification for paternalism in general.

 

Published inPatient CareUncategorized